skip to Main Content

Recovering Moses: The Contribution of Eric Voegelin and Contemporary Political Science

Introduction

The purpose of this essay is to examine the legacy of Moses as a political leader in search of political order.  The Mosaic conflict with the Pharaonic world is of great significance to politics, although it has not attracted much interest from political scientists.  This field of study demands highly developed research skills in areas usually considered beyond the pale for the contemporary political scientist.  There is also the practical consideration that studies in the area of the Ancient Near East are usually “off limits” for students of politics who often restrict their analysis to the contemporary world.  Robert McAfee Brown, a prominent theologian, humorously introduced his review of Michael Walzer’s Exodus and Revolution in this tone: “What, pray tell, is a political philosopher up to, offering judgments on the interpretation of biblical and Midrashic texts, events of Protestant church history and contemporary Roman Catholic theologies of liberation?”[1]  Brown continued his sardonic review by noting that Walzer’s tome could be considered to be “a brash invasion of his distinctive turf.”[2]  We will examine three recent works by contemporary political scientists and compare their efforts to Eric Voegelin’s groundbreaking Israel and Revelation, published fifty years ago.  Our comparisons will concentrate on the theophanic or revelatory event and how the recovery of this idea, regardless of how is it manifested, is essential to an understanding of the political order of the Ancient Near East.  Voegelin remains a prominent figure in the postwar study of political science, especially political theory, and the critical relationship of reason and revelation in his work deserves even more attention than it has received.[3]  In this survey we will try to present the differences and similarities of these theorists, and finally, argue that Voegelin’s approach remains more useful than the others.

The difficulties involved in this type of research have already been elucidated to some degree; it is compounded by the divergent trends that are prominent in contemporary biblical scholarship generally, and in the estimation of Moses in particular.  One approach currently in vogue, for example, is “aimed at devaluating the Moses tradition almost to the verge of eliminating him from the magnificent gallery of historic persons described in the Old Testament.”[4]  Other approaches, as one might imagine, attempt to preserve the older view of Moses as an integral figure in the history of Israel.  The scholarship of Eric Voegelin and the other political scientists we will encounter in course of this essay lead us toward a more accurate presentation of Moses and offer a portrait of the prophet Moses that is of importance today.  In other words, we are no longer forced to side with the historical-critical approach of contemporary biblical scholarship or to reject all critical methodologies, but are free to reassess Moses in a new light.[5]

Wildavsky and Moses as Political Scientist

Aaron Wildavsky’s The Nursing Father: Moses as a Political Leader is the most important recent work by a political scientist on Moses.[6]  It is even more fascinating when we consider Wildavsky’s reputation as a student of politics was based on his work in the field of public policy where his accomplishments were significant.  His text, The Politics of the Budgetary Process, remains a seminal work in the fields of public administration and public policy.  Wildavsky’s impetus to pursue a study of Moses was based on religious concerns.[7]  As an American Jew, he was attempting to trace his patrimony.  The student riots of the 1960s exhibited for Wildavsky an extreme example of political fanaticism and he wondered if this energy could have been directed towards a greater, moral good.  He wanted a “fanaticism of insistence, of reiteration, and pure will”[8] and he found what he believed was greatest example of such a force in Moses.  The Mosaic tradition, for Wildavsky, was centered around the historical figure of Moses.  Moses’ errors are as important as his successes and the processes involved in Moses’ decision-making become the basis for this study.  Wildavsky’s The Nursing Father stresses the experiential element as the ground for all political knowledge, but ironically the author argues that Moses may not be so different from many individuals who assume positions of leadership in contemporary society.  Wildavsky’s Moses becomes a specimen of general leadership, instead of a model of a unique leader responding to a particular crisis.  Initially, we must question the presentation of the mundane Moses, removed from the Kosmos of the Ancient Near East and transposed on a larger world, who is no longer a leader of a people inspired by a theophanic experience, but Moses as an archetype of how leadership can be improved.

To evaluate the leadership qualities of Moses, Wildavsky assumes the methodology of the structural anthropologist.  He states his indifference to dissimilarities in chronology and stresses his desire to understand the “inner coherence” of Moses.  Wildvasky’s structural analysis, which is centered upon understanding society as a whole, becomes the model for the book.  Wildavsky’s initial distillation of his research design would also suggest some potential compatibility with Voegelin[9]

Barry Cooper has argued convincingly for a separation of the two approaches: “there are no insuperable barriers arising from his [Voegelin’s] broad interpretative strategy that would serve as effective means to prevent more focused and specialized corrections of fact or emphasis.”[10]  Voegelin’s interpretative method, in other words, is less vulnerable to contradiction and more empirical in scope.  Wildavsky’s reliance upon structural criticism and the related limitations of the middoth, the basis for rabbinical interpretation, prohibit him from thoroughly coming to terms with the biblical text.  The Moses of Exodus is interpreted as a personal chronicle, not as a collection of traditions that must be sorted and analyzed.  The Moses of the Deuteronomic Torah now becomes a less convincing figure.

Wildavsky proceeds to point to the four periods of Mosaic leadership: slavery, anarchy, equity, and hierarchy.  The central element of Wildavsky’s study becomes an effort to present Moses as a model for leadership.  The challenges to Moses are political in nature and these four periods also refer to the crises Moses must encounter.  In the first period of Mosaic leadership, slavery, we are introduced to Wildavsky’s use of contemporary political science methods to make his argument.  He refers to Moses in this period as the passive leader of a passive people, borrowing in part from James David Barber’s analysis of contemporary American presidential leadership.[11]  Moses becomes a “mirror” of his people and exudes a passivity in all affairs, and this personality “type” is connected to a level of performance.[12]  The thornbush incident is construed as a threat to Moses from the divine.  This account unfortunately disregards the response by Moses to the revelatory act.  When the literary situation is examined, Moses’ noticeable openness to the message is revealed; his reluctance to participate dissipates and he realizes the seriousness of the challenge presented to him.[13]  Wildavsky’s diffident approach to biblical criticism makes his scholarly enterprise more problematic, but it is Wildavsky’s reluctance to appreciate the centrality of the theophanic experience in the life of Moses that is the most profound weakness of this work.

There appears to be a conscious effort on the part of Wildavsky to devaluate the manifestation of a radical transcendence among the people of Israel.  Wildavsky suggests the revelatory force may be counterproductive: “The importance of divine intervention diminishes throughout the Bible.  Only when Moses frees himself from it and accepts the human need to wrestle with history can he begin to free his people from the moral and mental fetters of slavery.”[14]  Throughout two of the four periods in which Moses must lead, revelation is reduced to either a personal experience with the divine or it is relegated to a conflict among various gods.  The appropriate response—for Wildavsky’s Moses—is to resist outside intervention, especially during the period he calls the anarchy model.  If pushed to its logical extreme, this version of Moses resembles a modern day congressman, amassing support from various interests, but remaining aloof as not to become attached to one source of power.  He must constantly change his positions because the world around him is adjusting to different types of political regimes.  Moses becomes a commonplace figure, and as we have demonstrated, this can not be reconciled with Moses who serves as the mediator of the divine word as it has been communicated through history.  Wildavsky’s Moses is a product of late twentieth century political science and its approach to political leadership.  As a defense of the biblical “view” of leadership, the work is an enlightening enterprise, perhaps the best example of a study of political personality to be presented in years.  But the search for Moses must go beyond a depiction of Moses as the political scientist who spends his time “discovering new coalitions of interests, arranging mutually advantageous trades, and otherwise expanding the bargaining network.”[15]

Walzer and Moses as Revolutionary Leader

For a political theorist who has spent most of his life pleading the case for democracy, Michael Walzer has an unusual predilection for reinterpreting people and events he believes are revolutionary.  Most of his research has involved what he considers to be revolutionary movements in religion; The Revolution of the Saints, a critique of the “radical” political theory of the puritans;[16]and Just and Unjust Wars, an historical survey and commentary on the problems of war, are examples of this tendency.  In the latter, Walzer develops a theory of “immeasurable evil” that argues for a limitation of the just war theory as an element of strategic thinking.  In his scholarship involving the Hebrew Bible, especially, Exodus and Revolution, Walzer posits that the Book of Exodus is a revolutionary document and that Moses is a reluctant revolutionary.  Liberation is presented as a continual process to be perpetuated even in the promised land.  To draw such a conclusion Walzer is forced to present the Sinaitic experience as an individualistic exercise.  Yahweh is, of course, speaking to a people, but he is most importantly speaking to the each person in the community.  The Berith is not for eternity, but it is an agreement that must be ratified regularly if it is to be maintained.  The accessibility and interpretation of sacred texts must be widespread because these works are for all the people; Walzer is refuting the claim made on the behalf esoteric writing by some political scientists and he is seeking to defend the Torah as a common document.  The reading of the document is so central to the survival of the community that individuals are required to discuss it publicly.[17]

Unlike the account of Moses in Exodus, Walzer’s characterization presents him as a man with “a reluctant sense of duty.”[18]  As with Wildavsky, Moses becomes divorced from the revelatory component of the biblical narrative: “Moses, after all, is not a messiah; he is a political leader who succeeds in bringing the Israelites out of Egypt but is unable to bring them to the promised land. Nor is the promised land the same thing as the messianic kingdom.”[19]

Walzer’s Moses must relinquish any religious significance he might have earned because it is incidental.  The spiritual and revelatory persona of Moses is subjugated to the idea of Moses the political leader.  When Moses is mediating the cause of his people before God, he is for Walzer acting as a political figure not as a religious authority.  The ramifications are obvious: the Book of Exodus can no longer be an account of deliverance, it is a work of political history.  Walzer sees the great leader of the Israelites as a Christlike figure, but he resembles the Messiah only to the degree that he seeks political objectives.  Moses, who traditionally is presented as an idealist, usually dreaming of the spiritual, surrenders to Moses the ancient insurgent.  Walzer is most impressed by the revolutionary’s ability to succeed in all endeavors.  Regardless of the controversy, Moses always prevails.

Walzer’s account of Moses and Exodus appeals to secular political activists who would like to have the divine sanction for their positions and activities without having to carry the spiritual and theological baggage that must accompany it, but the separation cannot be made so easily. The most vexatious aspect of Walzer’s study concerns his tendency to divorce his Moses the liberator from the biblical Moses.  The account of Moses contained in Exodus, one that witnesses the theophanic experiences of Moses and his brutality as a political leader, cannot be reconciled with Walzer’s version.  As Voegelin reminds us, it is to the memory of the people of Israel we must turn: “And in the continuity of Israel’s memory these events are inseparable from Moses, as the human instrument of Yahweh, as the prophet (nabi) from the midst of the brethren to whom the people shall hearken (Deut. 18:15).”[20]

Eidelberg and the Great Turn

Paul Eidelberg’s Jerusalem vs. Athens is a work of personal discovery.[21]  He has taught political science for many years in the United States and his Philosophy of the American Constitution and his A Discourse on Statesmanship are recognized as pioneering works.[22] Over two decades ago he moved to Israel and he currently teaches at Bar Ilan University.  Eidelberg’s early scholarship evinces the influence of his teacher, Leo Strauss.  His critique of the American constitution stressed that the document was a reaffirmation of the classical approach to excellence and moderation.

Like his mentor Strauss (and Tertullian), Eidelberg believes Athens and Jerusalem are the two great centers of civilization; however, the theophanic event for Strauss, as well as the role of reason, was to be understood as something superior to mere self-reflection.  The Bible and the contribution of the Greeks can justly claim to be true wisdom, but only at the cost of denying the validity of the other.  Strauss believed such a conflict between reason and revelation was good and served as the fundamental equalizing notion between the two sources of insight: “there has been a secular conflict within the West from its very beginning and that this conflict is the secret of the vitality of the West.”[23]

Jerusalem vs. Athens serves as a Eidelberg’s departure from the “Straussian” approach to revelation and the Hebrew Bible.  Eidelberg asserts that true revelation is the most rational expression possible, but to fully understand the distinction one must disregard the old dichotomy of Jerusalem, the defender of revelation, in conflict with Athens, the defender of reason.  For Eidelberg, the force of Elohim (Creation-God of Nature) and HaShem (Tetragrammatic God of revelation) must be combined to unite humanity.  Existence becomes a product of ratiocination and the grace of HaShem.[24]  The “pernicious”[25] reason-revelation division that was defended by Strauss must be overcome.  Strauss’s divisions are “not only superficial; they are a distortion of the truth…the Athenian tree of knowledge, with the tree of life, yields madness and death.”[26]  Revelation becomes for Eidelberg the greatest force in history, superior to the abilities of modern science as a means of improving the status of man.  The greatest man, the exemplar or Eidelberg’s philosopher-king, is Moses:

“The greatest figure in human history . . . a man who was at once a founder, legislator, and educator—combining wisdom, and power—is Moses.”[27]

“Consider, too, Moses’ other admirable qualities, for example, his indomitable courage, his unequaled perseverance.  Not only was he the educator of his people, but he was their leader and defender.”[28]

Moses represents a transcendence of the mundane because he has been chosen by the God and is given a special knowledge of humankind so he can understand “all men and all conditions of human life.”[29]  Moses is allowed to approach the Tree of Knowledge and observe the unity of humanity and his view of the human condition is a “uniform perspective of the HaShem as crystalized.”[30]  For we moderns to approach this understanding of life we also must approach the Tree—what Eidelberg describes as his General Theory of Existence—and the only source for this standard is the Torah.  If properly assimilated, this allows anyone to determine the adequacy of any doctrine.

Eidelberg’s work is a remarkable piece of erudition and a convincing defense of Moses as the greatest person who ever lived. Moses is, after all, the only human who has conversed with HaShem “mouth to mouth.”[31]  The historical Moses is a great figure, but Eidelberg’s Moses cannot really be human. He accepts the Talmudic descriptions without reservation and extends them beyond their logical limit.  Moses was not, as Eidelberg suggests, the founder of a religion.  The proper assessment of Moses must include some limitations, as Voegelin notes: “historical substance has been formed by the biblical narrative quite frequently for the very purpose of heightening paradigmatically its essential meaning . . .”[32]  The methodological consequences of accepting Eidelberg’s Moses are tremendous and costly.  At the minimum, one must disregard any “stratification of forms” in the Biblical account.  Eidelberg’s Moses helps us appreciate the right order of political existence, but he also serves as a mild distraction and is the byproduct of a grafted tradition.  When we remove the Moses who serves as the speaker of the Deuteronomic Torah, which as Voegelin argues, is the product of a mythical imagination, we again have Moses the source of mediation—a Moses unacceptable to Professor Eidelberg.

 Voegelin’s Moses

Eric Voegelin’s scholarship represents one of the most ambitious scholarly undertakings of the 20th century: Voegelin’s mission, a civilizing one, is in part an effort to show we moderns a path whereby we might overcome the chaos of our current existence.  Through his research, Voegelin addressed many of the most essential questions of political experience.  The first three volumes of his magnum opus, Order and History, began as a search for order in history.  These volumes stressed the ongoing “leaps in being” and the influences these leaps have had on humankind’s “new life.”  History, while not reduced to the single straight line of the Hegelian Weltgeist, was presented as a “progession of tension.”[33]  Voegelin intended Order and History to include a study of Christianity, but at an early juncture he realized that “one could not properly understand the Christian beginnings without going into the Jewish background.”[34]  Voegelin soon began studying Hebrew while he was teaching at the University of Alabama and acquired a propensity for translating the language.[35]  Voegelin’s philological abilities are unique for a political scientist and they provide the basis for much of the intricacy of his work.  But Voegelin’s approach to biblical studies has attracted some criticism.  A capricious reviewer has argued that Voegelin: “takes for granted that he understands the biblical authors better than they understood themselves.”[36]  Obviously, the writer has mistaken Voegelin’s attempt to understand the author of a sacred text as he understood himself.  Such attacks are balanced by the praise his approach to the Hebrew Bible has won from eminent biblical scholars like Bernhard Anderson who compared Israel and Revelation‘s “grappling with the problematic interrelation of the divine and human order” with Augustine’s The City of God.[37]

Voegelin’s Moses is a transitional figure, connecting the relatively compact world of Memphite theology to Christianity.  This new, differentiated field of experience is the most important break with the older order, but the role of Moses is epochal:

“The unique position of Moses has resisted clasification by type concepts, as well as articulation through the symbols of the Biblical tradition. He moves in a peculiar empty space between the old Pharonic and the new collective sons of God, between the Egyptian empire and the Israelite theopolity. On the obscurities surrounding the position of Moses now falls a flood rather than a ray of light, if we recognize in him the man who, in the order of revelation, prefigured, but did not figurate himself, the Son of God.”[38]

Voegelin argued this symbolization could be understood as an effort to “overcome” the compactness of the Egyptian order and advance the movement towards the more highly developed Christian period.  Through Moses and the messianic symbolism attached to him, we have the beginning of the “divine order” that results in Jesus.  Moses embodies the characteristics of the “Son of God,” although he is reluctant to accept the challenge of the charge.  The “Son of God” is more than the figure of Moses, but it includes the movement from Egypt, which Moses leads.  Moses must also organize and guide a group of people who have refrained from making the necessary sacrifices and commitments for the sojourn out of Egypt.  At one juncture his followers accuse Moses of attempting to kill them on the journey and ask him to return to Egypt.[39]  Moses perseveres and regains his control of a skeptical lot.  So we find in Moses, the seeker of order, the basis for a transformation of a clan of Hebrews into the divinely-inspired nation.  Moses can undertake such a mission precisely because he experienced the theophanic reality, and Israel as the “Son of God” could have never existed had it not been for Moses.  As Voegelin notes: “There never would have been a first-born son of Yahweh if the God had had to rely on the people alone; . . . it had its origin in Moses.”[40]  The creation of Israel is the experience of Moses’ “leap in being,” his extraordinary advance in perception that he shares with the Israelites.  This presence allowed the people of Israel to understand the human condition more thoroughly than any previous civilization had been able to understand it.

The expatriation of the Israelites marks the decline of the Pharaonic order.  Egypt is no longer the most favored empire and it must surrender its status in the world.  Yahweh forces the Pharaoh to relinquish his title of the “Son of God” and it is assumed by Israel; therefore, it is no longer bestowed on a single individual.  Egypt can never again exert the control it possessed in the past.  The Pharaoh, in an effort to save his kingdom, appeals to Moses and Aaron to depart quickly and promises not to attempt to follow the émigrés.[41]  For Voegelin, “The Egypt after the Exodus will not be the same as before, for now a greater power than the Pharaonic will have been recognized.”[42]

The new “Son of God” is a coherent social movement, but the group is again unable to provide the necessary leadership to make the departure from Egypt.  It is at this point that we notice a more differentiated symbolism making its appearance: the revelation to Moses in Exodus 2 and 3.  In Exodus 2:15-25 the Pharaoh dies and people of Israel remain in bondage and continue to pray for deliverance.  Moses has fled Egypt and is in the land of Midian.  In Midian the God of the Fathers reveals himself and tells Moses he will serve as the leader for the removal of the people of Israel from Egypt.  In verse 25 the condition of the people of Israel is acknowledged by God as a reaffirmation of the Mosaic call.  Voegelin argues Yahweh was already a recognized deity, thereby affirming a procession of symbols that were in the process of change.  Yahweh’s entrusting of the fate of Israel to Moses indicates the importance of the revelation.  The procession of tension through Exodus 2 marks the awakening of Moses to his competition with the Egyptian regime.  He has no alternative except to assume the mantel of leadership and suffer the consequences of his decision.[43]  The divinity expresses himself through his actions and these events are evidenced by the instances where we are told “God knew” of the situation of the Israelites.  God is presented as always participating in human history and maintaining a desire to improve humanity, albeit he does not always take an active role in these activities.

The revelatory acts are the most prominent example of the continuation of the Berith that can be found in the Old Testament.  The covenant is renewed and ratified by the thornbush experience of Exodus 3:14; the “mutual presence of God and Moses in the thornbush dialogue will then have expanded into the mutual presence of God and his people.”[44]  A troublesome aspect of the encounter neglected by Voegelin is the manifestation of the divine to Moses—it is ehyeh, not Yahweh.  When Moses returns to the Israelites he tells his people “Ehyeh has sent me to you.”[45]  The patrimony of the Yahweh’s name is not a major concern of this essay, but it explains why one can be inconclusive about the different representations of the divine in the thornbush pericope.  Voegelin argues that the meaning of the name Yahweh is unknown and he asserts its relationship might actually be closer to ehyeh than most contemporary biblical scholars are willing admit.  The most important consideration is the outburst, which indicates it is not an unintelligible act, but a remnant of the compactness of the older order.  The hidden God in the thornbrush reveals the connection of God, through Moses, and the new constitution of being.  The people and the divine can no longer be separated and their historical constitution is revived through this event.

The problem of the mysterium that possesses both tremendum and fascinang is perplexing; we are confronted by a hidden “adonai” who breaks the older perception so completely as to suggest the need for a reappraisal: “The tension between the hidden depth in God and his manifestations has been transposed, by thornbush episode, from the form of cosmological myth to the form of revealed presence in history.”[46]  Moses, as the medium for the divine word, as it was revealed to him, becomes a historical figure and the perpetuity of the sacred text is established.

Above all, a certain sense of balance prevails and the continuity advances our understanding of the figure of Moses, according to Voegelin:

“Moreover, the parallel is accentuated through the climactic episodes: The declaration of Israel as the Son of God balances the destruction of the first-born of Egypt; the enigmatic night scene, in which Moses is almost killed by Yahweh, balances the Red Sea disaster in which the strength of the Egyptian Son of God is actually engulfed.  Only through the overlaying construction of the whole narrative can we find the great issue–that would disappear if the component episodes were taken in isolation—that is, the transition of historical order from the Empire to the Chosen People.”[47]

The new order consists of the people of God and the revelatory act involving Moses, which has been shared with his people.  Moses’ struggles are the struggles of the people of Israel.  The more multifaceted the conflict Moses encounters, the more multifaceted the existence of Chosen People become.  The Sitz in Leben of the leader translates into the actual setting of his people.  Voegelin’s critique refutes the claims of his critics who describe him as a textual scholar who usually: “tends to agree with the skepticism inherent in the modern historical consciousness concerning the reliability of the account of the events in the Pentateuch.”[48]   On the contrary, Voegelin is presenting the problem of Moses with clarity and sympathy.  Lynn Clapham’s critique of Voegelin’s Moses suggests the weaknesses of Voegelin’s approach may be that he simply did not elucidate his insights to the fullest degree possible.  For example, the thornbush incident is the beginning of the relationship between and divine and the Moses, but Voegelin should have stressed the continuity between Yahweh and the “God of your fathers” as it appears in Exodus 3 and 6.  This is, in other words, a promulgation of the promises of the deity in the past.[49]  The weakness of Clapham’s criticism lies in a refusal to assimilate Voegelin’s depiction of the continuity of experience among the Israelites. When the Yahwist order is threatened by the Omride policy of alliances the need for a new leader becomes imminent.[50]  The problematic element of this situation that Clapham does exclude from consideration is not Moses as the successor, but the problem of Mosaic succession.

Voegelin alludes to the potential dilemma: “. . . Moses is the man who has freed Israel from the polytheism and superstition and brought it into the presence of the one God.  The function of his prophetic successors is less clear.”[51]  Clapham’s criticism of Voegelin’s portrayal of the Sinai Berith deserves more attention.  Clapham also notes that the recent scholarship of Mendenhall and Baltzer present a view of the Berith not so different from the contemporary approach to and understanding of the term today.[52]  This form, as Clapham observes: “uses a history of benevolence as the basis for vassal obligation to the apodictic law.”[53]  The discovery of this form unites many of Voegelin’s concerns with legal and cultic procedures identified in Exodus 19-24.  Clapham’s observations are an endorsement of Voegelin’s analysis of the Mosaic era and augment Voegelin’s description of the changing symbolization of period.[54]  Voegelin’s Moses remains the most accurate account we have to work with and our sources are again limited to the biblical narrative.

It should be mentioned that Voegelin’s account of Moses contains some important limitations.  His characterization is, as the reader can understand, much different from most accounts, even the sources Voegelin praises in Israel and Revelation.  He has avoided the temptation to reconstruct Moses as a paradigmatic figure in the fashion of Martin Buber.  Voegelin also recognizes the textual limitations: “Of the man who has created history as the present under God no ‘historical’ image can be drawn, as no sources in the convention sense are extant.”[55]

Voegelin seeks to delinate a more accurate assessment of Moses by questioning some of the material usually attributed to him.  He finds the tradition of ascribing Mosaic authorship to the Dueteronomic code troublesome and suggests: “They (sixth century Israelites) must have known that what they held in hand was not the ‘Torah of Moses,’ but a literary production conceived and written by one or more members of their own group no longer than a generation ago.”[56]  As a result, much of the early accounts of Moses in the J and E narratives are inaccurate according to Voegelin.  So the presentation of Moses as the historian and speaker of the Deuteronomic discourses is a product of a “mythical imagination” and the problem is increased when one considers the claims made for Mosaic authorship of the Pentateuchal Torah.[57]  If Voegelin’s commentary is correct, the ramifications are substantial.  The Moses of Deuteronomy 11:26-29, the nearly godlike figure who presents the Israeli people with the prospects of a blessing and a curse, can be dismissed.  Moses is, after all, one of the people and they are ammi, “my people.”  The separation is surely imposed and Voegelin correctly attributes this to later sources.[58]

Voegelin’s Moses is the result of a thorough and scientific exegesis of the source materials from many areas.[59]  Moses is not the historian of Deuteronomy, but he is a spiritual founder—although Voegelin suggests Moses is not the founder of a religion.  He has offset the criticisms Clapman presented and reaffirmed his “terse” formula: “Yahweh brought Israel, through Moses, up from Egypt.”[60]  Most profoundly, Moses serves as the nabi, the man in whose heart and mind the “leap of being” occurs.  Moses is no longer for Voegelin a messenger of the Berith, but the medium for the message.  Moses is the stimulus for the sign of the divine as he unites the order of the people in the present with the divine rhythm of existence.  Man must continue to profess his devotion to the divine to preserve his relationship and through Moses the presentation of this reverence is permitted.

Voegelin’s Moses also shares a legislative quality.  He frequently presents decisions for the welfare his people and through personal persuasion demonstrates a propensity for solving disputes.  Moses serves as an arbitrator, attempting to reconcile factors unwilling to settle quarrels within the people of Israel.  Moses is depicted in Israel and Revelation as the recorder of memorable events, but not as the historian of his people.[61]  Voegelin ascribes a fourth classification to Moses—that of a liberator.  He brought his people out of a state of slavery into a condition of political freedom, but as Voegelin accounts, Moses “was not an Israelite Giribaldi, for the people, in order to be freed by him from the bondage of Pharaoh, had to enter the service of Yahweh.”[62]  Moses must be distinguished from the modern proponents of liberation theology who seek to expand the political and limit the role of the sacred in social life.[63]  Voegelin’s limited “liberator” is a reformer, although he possesses an element of restraint.  He is also able to translate the transcendental tension in the life of the nation of Israel into a triumph in this world in the form of a kingdom in Canaan.  Moses’ soul has been awakened to the pneumatic differentiation—a sense of the divine apart from creation—and it is able to discern the emerging transcendent element between the divine and the earthly realms.[64]  Voegelin summarizes his critique of Moses by suggesting: “[Moses] has given Israel its constitution as the people under God in historical existence.”[65]

The Rediscovery of Moses

We have assumed a critical position in regards to the three images of Moses we have compared to Voegelin’s account.  Wildavsky, Walzer and Eidelberg, have made a contribution to our understanding and are to be commended for their efforts to move beyond the normal parochialism that dominates many academic disciplines in America.  All of the works examined in this essay are attempts to reclaim Holy Scripture and the figure of Moses as an appropriate subject for political scientists to study.

If there is to be a revival of interest in the Hebrew Bible in general and Moses specifically, it must be guided by an ontological understanding of the political order—it should also include a philosophy of being which will allow a more thorough understanding of the role of theophanic event in the life of Israel.  Voegelin’s Israel and Revelation can continue to serve as the starting point for such an enterprise.

 

Notes

The author wishes to thank David J. Walsh, James M. Miclot, Dennis Horton, and two anonymous reviewers for their comments on an earlier version of this essay.  Research support from the Earhart Foundation provided the author with the opportunity to prepare the manuscript for publication.

[1] Robert McAfee Brown, “A Bible of the Oppressed,” New York Review of Books, 20 January 1985.

[2] Ibid.

[3] There are some notable exceptions to the trend.  See Michael P. Federici, Eric Voegelin: The Restoration of Order (Wilmington, Delaware: I.S.I. Books, 2002); David J. Walsh, After Ideology: Recovering the Spiritual Foundations of Freedom (San Francisco: HarperSanFrancisco, 1990; reprinted, Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 1996 ), and Guarded By Mystery (Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 1999), and The Third Millenium: Reflections on Faith and Reason (Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press, 1999); Thomas W. Heilke, Eric Voegelin: In Quest of Reality (Lanham, Maryland: Rowman and Littlefield, 1999); Barry Cooper, Eric Voegelin and the Foundations of Modern Political Science (Columbia: University of Missouri Press, 1999); and James Rhodes’ “Philosophy, Revelation, and Political Theory,” Journal of Politics, Volume 49, Number 4 (November 1987), pp. 1036-1060.  For the integration of Voegelin’s approach to revelation with a critique of the limits of contemporary biblical scholarship’s openness to theophanic expression, see Maurice P. Hogan, The Biblical Vision of the Human Person (Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang, 1994).

[4] Eduard Nielsen, “Moses and the Law,” Vetus Testamentum XXXII, 1 (1982), pp. 87-98.

[5] The standard criticism of the texts involving Moses went as follows:  there are four sources—J(9th Century B.C.-half a chapter of text), E (8th Century B.C.), D (7th Century B.C.), and  P (6th-5th Centuries B.C.—the largest source).  Voegelin’s reliance upon historical-critical scholarship is a subject worthy of additional scholarly analysis.  See Maurice P. Hogan, “Editor’s Introduction,” Order and History, Volume 1: Israel and Revelation (Columbia, Missouri: University of Missouri Press, 2001), pp. 1-14 (hereafter cited as Israel and Revelation).

[6] University, Alabama: University of Alabama Press, 1984.

[7] His grandfather was a rabbi who was killed in the Nazi invasion of the Ukraine.  Both his paternal and maternal grandparents were Orthodox Jews.

[8] The Nursing Father, p. 4.

[9] Ibid., p. 15.

[10] Barry Cooper, The Political Theory of Eric Voegelin (New York: The Edwin Mellen Press, 1986), p. 154.

[11] James David Barber, The Presidential Character, Fourth Edition (New York: Prentice Hall, 1992).  Barber’s model is based on a “psychology of adaptation” through which presidents adjust to changing political situations.  The desire for progress, action and legitimacy become the major concerns of leadership.

[12] The Nursing Father, p. 31.

[13] Voegelin, Israel and Revelation, pp. 448-459.

[14] The Nursing Father, p. 181.

[15] The Nursing Father, p. 216.

[16] For a different, but related assessment critique to the concerns of this paper one should consult Eric Voegelin’s “Eine Formverwandtschaft mit der puritanishen Mystik,” Ueber die Form des amerikanischen Geistes (Tubingen: Mohr Verlag, 1928), pp. 120-171, or the more recent English translation of this work in the The Collected Works of Eric Voegelin, Volume 1 [Columbia, Missouri: University of Missouri Press, 1995].

[17] Michael Walzer, Interpretation and Social Criticism (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1987), pp. 74-75.

[18] Ibid, p. 18.

[19] Michael Walzer, Exodus and Revolution (New York: Basic Books, 1985), p. 17.

[20] Eric Voegelin, Israel and Revelation, p. 432.

[21] Jerusalem vs. Athens: In Quest of a General Theory of Existence (Lanham, Maryland: University Press of America, 1983).

[22] The Philosophy of the Constitution (New York: The Free Press, 1968), and A Discourse on Statesmanship (Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1974).

[23] Leo Strauss, “Jersusalem and Athens,” in Studies in Platonic Political Philosophy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983).

[24] Jerusalem vs. Athens, p. 61.

[25] Ibid.

[26] Ibid., p. 23.

[27] Ibid., p. 46.

[28] Ibid., p. 48.

[29] Ibid., p. 157.

[30] Ibid., p. 156.

[31] Jerusalem vs. Athens, p. 323.

[32] Voegelin, Israel and Revelation, pp. 433-434.

[33] See Gerhart Niemeyer, “Eric Voegelin’s Philosophy and the Drama of Mankind,” Modern Age, Volume 20, Number 1 (Winter 1976), p. 29, for a greater discussion of this theme of tension.

[34] Eric Voegelin, Autobiographical Reflections (Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University Press, 1989), p. 63.

[35] Ibid.

[36] Raymond Weiss, “Voegelin’s Biblical Hermeneutics,” Independent Journal of Philosophy, Volume 5/6 (1988), p. 82.

[37] Bernhard W. Anderson, “Politics and the Transcendent: Voegelin’s Philosophical and Theological Exposition of the Old Testament in the Context of the Ancient Near East,” in Stephen A. McKnight, ed., Eric Voegelin’s Search for Order in History (Lanham, Maryland: University Press of America, 1987), p. 64.

[38] Voegelin, Israel and Revelation, p. 450.

[39] Exodus 14:11-12.

[40] Voegelin, Israel and Revelation, p. 443.

[41] Exodus 12.

[42] Voegelin, Israel and Revelation, p. 442.

[43] Ibid., p. 452-454.

[44] Ibid., p. 459.

[45] Ibid.

[46] Ibid., p. 466.

[47] Ibid., p. 470.

[48] Weiss, Ibid., p. 82.

[49] Lynn Clapman, “Voegelin and Hebrew Scripture: Israel and Revelation in Retrospect,” in John Kirby and William Thompson, eds., Voegelin and the Theologian: Ten Studies in Interpretation (New York: The Edwin Mellen Press, 1983), pp.104-137.

[50] Voegelin, “The Deuteronomic Torah,” Israel and Revelation, pp. 405-430.

[51] Ibid., p. 422.

[52] See George Mendenhall, The Tenth Generation: The Origins of the Biblical Tradition (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1973), especially Chapter VII, “Tribe and State in the Ancient World.”

[53] Clapham, Ibid., p. 124.

[54] In the prophetic period, Clapham again attempts to enhance Voegelin’s approach by offering a more elaborate definition of the new symbolization.  Clapham believes the impetus for the articulation of the new symbols is more diverse than Voegelin’s account—namely, Clapham would include the “ambassadors” from Yahweh’s court, the witnesses to Yahweh’s acts, and the members of the divine council.

[55] Voegelin, Israel and Revelation, p. 431.

[56] Ibid., p. 413.

[57] Ibid., p. 434.

[58] Moses’s efforts could also be diminished by the activities of his people.  In other words, a defection of sorts from the instructions of Yahweh could destroy the nation before it is really established (See Israel and Revelation, pp. 406-407).

[59] Voegelin considered himself a scientist and keep abreast of develops in all the fields of study related to his work.  In his Autobiographical Reflections, Voegelin noted, after reflecting on his lifelong interest in science that  “Biological theory has remained one of my permanent interests, just as physics has so remained from my initial start on the problems in my last years of high school” (p. 25).

[60] Voegelin, Israel and Revelation, p. 440.

[61] For Voegelin, Moses is more than the prophet one encounters in contemporary biblical scholarship; he is a significant participant in the world around him and has much influence on that environment.

[62] Israel and Revelation, p. 440.

[63] This is not a new proposition, but it has acquired more adherents.  One must in part credit the French ideologues, who claimed to be an empirical lot, but in actuality were not.  The approaches of Comte and de Tracy to the world of politics may not be so different from contemporary liberation theologians.

[64] See Eugene Webb, “Eric Voegelin’s Theory of Revelation,” The Thomist 42 (1978), which expands upon the brief assessment presented here.

[65] Voegelin, Israel and Revelation, p. 480.

Avatar photo

Lee Cheek is a Board Member of VoegelinView and Professor of Political Science and the former Dean of the School of Social Sciences at East Georgia State College, and a Senior Fellow of Alexander Hamilton Institute. His books include Calhoun and Popular Rule (University of Missouri Press, 2001), Order and Legitimacy (Transaction/Rutgers, 2004; reprinted, Routledge, 2017), and Confronting Modernity (Wesley Studies Society, 2011), among others.

Back To Top